-[WAVE FUNCTION] COLLAPSE-

-in ‘quantum mechanix’, ‘wave function collapse’ occurs when a ‘wave function’ — initially in a ‘super-position’ of several ‘eigen-states’ — reduces to a single ‘eigen-state’ due to ‘inter-action’ with the ‘external world’-

.

This interaction is called an “observation”.

It is the essence of a measurement in ‘quantum mechanics’ which connects the wave function with classical observables like position and momentum.

Collapse is one of two processes by which quantum systems evolve in time;

the other is the continuous evolution via the Schrödinger equation.[1]

Collapse is a black box for a thermodynamically irreversible interaction with a classical environment

Calculations of quantum decoherence show that when a quantum system interacts with the environment, the superpositions apparently reduce to mixtures of classical alternatives.

Significantly, the combined wave function of the system and environment continue to obey the Schrödinger equation.[4]

More importantly, this is not enough to explain wave function collapse, as decoherence does not reduce it to a single eigen-state

In 1927, Werner Heisenberg used the idea of wave function reduction to explain quantum measurement

However, if collapse were a fundamental physical phenomenon, rather than just the epiphenomenon of some other process, it would mean nature was fundamentally stochastic, i.e. nondeterministic, an undesirable property for a theory

Contents

1 Mathematical description
1.1 Mathematical background
1.2 The process of collapse
1.3 Quantum decoherence
2 History and context
3 See also
4 Notes
5 References
6 External links

.

Mathematical description

Before collapse, the wave function may be any square-integrable function.

This function is expressible as a linear combination of the eigenstates of any observable.

Observables represent classical dynamical variables, and when one is measured by a classical observer, the wave function is projected onto a random eigenstate of that observable.

The observer simultaneously measures the classical value of that observable to be the eigenvalue of the final state

Mathematical background

For an explanation of the notation used, see bra–ket notation.

For details on this formalism, see quantum state.

The quantum state of a physical system is described by a wave function (in turn—an element of a projective Hilbert space). This can be expressed as a vector using Dirac or bra–ket notation :

{\displaystyle |\psi \rangle =\sum {i}c{i}|\phi {i}\rangle .} | \psi \rangle = \sum_i c_i | \phi_i \rangle . The kets {\displaystyle |\phi {1}\rangle ,|\phi {2}\rangle ,|\phi {3}\rangle \cdots }{\displaystyle |\phi {1}\rangle ,|\phi {2}\rangle ,|\phi _{3}\rangle \cdots }, specify the different quantum “alternatives” available—a particular quantum state. They form an orthonormal eigenvector basis, formally

{\displaystyle \langle \phi {i}|\phi {j}\rangle =\delta {ij}.}\langle \phi_i | \phi_j \rangle = \delta{ij}.
Where {\displaystyle \delta {ij}}\delta {ij} represents the Kronecker delta.

An observable (i.e. measurable parameter of the system) is associated with each eigenbasis, with each quantum alternative having a specific value or eigenvalue, ei, of the observable.

A “measurable parameter of the system” could be the usual position r and the momentum p of (say) a particle, but also its energy E, z components of spin (sz), orbital (Lz) and total angular (Jz) momenta etc. In the basis representation these are respectively {\displaystyle |\mathbf {r} ,t\rangle =|x,t\rangle +|y,t\rangle +|z,t\rangle ,|\mathbf {p} ,t\rangle =|p_{x},t\rangle +|p_{y},t\rangle +|p_{z},t\rangle ,|E\rangle ,|s_{z}\rangle ,|L_{z}\rangle ,|J_{z}\rangle ,\cdots }{\displaystyle |\mathbf {r} ,t\rangle =|x,t\rangle +|y,t\rangle +|z,t\rangle ,|\mathbf {p} ,t\rangle =|p_{x},t\rangle +|p_{y},t\rangle +|p_{z},t\rangle ,|E\rangle ,|s_{z}\rangle ,|L_{z}\rangle ,|J_{z}\rangle ,\cdots }.

The coefficients c1, c2, c3… are the probability amplitudes corresponding to each basis {\displaystyle |\phi {1}\rangle ,|\phi {2}\rangle ,|\phi {3}\rangle \cdots }{\displaystyle |\phi {1}\rangle ,|\phi {2}\rangle ,|\phi {3}\rangle \cdots }. These are complex numbers. The moduli square of ci, that is |ci|2 = cici ( denotes complex conjugate), is the probability of measuring the system to be in the state {\displaystyle |\phi {i}\rangle }|\phi {i}\rangle .

For simplicity in the following, all wave functions are assumed to be normalized; the total probability of measuring all possible states is one:

{\displaystyle \langle \psi |\psi \rangle =\sum {i}|c{i}|^{2}=1.}\langle \psi|\psi \rangle = \sum_i |c_i|^2 = 1.
The process of collapse
With these definitions it is easy to describe the process of collapse. For any observable, the wave function is initially some linear combination of the eigenbasis {\displaystyle {|\phi {i}\rangle }}{|\phi {i}\rangle } of that observable. When an external agency (an observer, experimenter) measures the observable associated with the eigenbasis {\displaystyle {|\phi {i}\rangle }}{|\phi {i}\rangle }, the wave function collapses from the full {\displaystyle |\psi \rangle }|\psi \rangle to just one of the basis eigenstates, {\displaystyle |\phi {i}\rangle }|\phi {i}\rangle , that is:

{\displaystyle |\psi \rangle \rightarrow |\phi {i}\rangle .}|\psi\rangle \rightarrow |\phi_i\rangle. The probability of collapsing to a given eigenstate {\displaystyle |\phi {k}\rangle }|\phi {k}\rangle is the Born probability, {\displaystyle P{k}=|c_{k}|^{2}}P_k=| c_k |^2 . Immediately post-measurement, other elements of the wave function vector, {\displaystyle c_{i\neq k}}c_{i\neq k}, have “collapsed” to zero, and {\displaystyle |c_{i}|^{2}=1}{\displaystyle |c_{i}|^{2}=1}.[note 1]

More generally, collapse is defined for an operator {\displaystyle {\hat {Q}}}{\hat {Q}} with eigenbasis {\displaystyle {|\phi {i}\rangle }}{|\phi {i}\rangle }. If the system is in state {\displaystyle |\psi \rangle }|\psi \rangle , and {\displaystyle {\hat {Q}}}{\hat {Q}} is measured, the probability of collapsing the system to eigenstate {\displaystyle |\phi {i}\rangle }|\phi {i}\rangle (and measuring the eigenvalue {\displaystyle q_{i}}q_{i} of {\displaystyle |\phi {i}\rangle }|\phi {i}\rangle with respect to {\displaystyle {\hat {Q}}}{\hat {Q}}) would be {\displaystyle |\langle \psi |\phi {i}\rangle |^{2}}|\langle \psi |\phi {i}\rangle |^{2}. Note that this is not the probability that the particle is in state {\displaystyle |\phi {i}\rangle }|\phi {i}\rangle ; it is in state {\displaystyle |\psi \rangle }|\psi \rangle until cast to an eigenstate of {\displaystyle {\hat {Q}}}{\hat {Q}}.

However, we never observe collapse to a single eigenstate of a continuous-spectrum operator (e.g. position, momentum, or a scattering Hamiltonian), because such eigenfunctions are non-normalizable.

In these cases, the wave function will partially collapse to a linear combination of “close” eigenstates (necessarily involving a spread in eigenvalues) that embodies the imprecision of the measurement apparatus.

The more precise the measurement, the tighter the range.

Calculation of probability proceeds identically, except with an integral over the expansion coefficient {\displaystyle c(q,t)dq}c (q, t) dq.[8]

This phenomenon is unrelated to the uncertainty principle, although increasingly precise measurements of one operator (e.g. position) will naturally homogenize the expansion coefficient of wave function with respect to another, incompatible operator (e.g. momentum), lowering the probability of measuring any particular value of the latter.

Quantum decoherence
Main article: Quantum decoherence

Quantum decoherence explains why a system interacting with an environment transitions from being a pure state, exhibiting superpositions, to a mixed state, an incoherent combination of classical alternatives.

This transition is fundamentally reversible, as the combined state of system and environment is still pure, but for all practical purposes irreversible, as the environment is a very large and complex quantum system, and it is not feasible to reverse their interaction.

Decoherence is thus very important for explaining the classical limit of quantum mechanics, but cannot explain wave function collapse, as all classical alternatives are still present in the mixed state, and wave function collapse selects only one of them

History and context

The concept of wavefunction collapse was introduced by Werner Heisenberg in his 1927 paper on the uncertainty principle,

“Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik”,

and incorporated into the mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics by John von Neumann, in his 1932 treatise Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik.[10]

Heisenberg did not try to specify exactly what the collapse of the wavefunction meant.

He, however, emphasized that it should not be understood as a physical process.[11]

Niels Bohr also repeatedly cautioned that we must give up a “pictorial representation.

” The founders of the Copenhagen Interpretation preferred to stress the mathematical formalism of what was occurring

.

Consistent with Heisenberg, von Neumann postulated that there were 2 processes of wave function change:

The probabilistic, non-unitary, non-local, discontinuous change brought about by observation and measurement, as outlined above.

The deterministic, unitary, continuous time evolution of an isolated system that obeys the Schrödinger equation

(or a relativistic equivalent, i.e. the Dirac equation)

.

In general, quantum systems exist in superpositions of those basis states that most closely correspond to classical descriptions, and, in the absence of measurement, evolve according to the Schrödinger equation.

However, when a measurement is made, the wave function collapses—from an observer’s perspective—to just one of the basis states, and the property being measured uniquely acquires the eigenvalue of that particular state, {\displaystyle \lambda {i}}\lambda {i}.

After the collapse, the system again evolves according to the Schrödinger equation.

By explicitly dealing with the interaction of object and measuring instrument, von Neumann[1] has attempted to create consistency of the two processes of wave function change.

He was able to prove the possibility of a quantum mechanical measurement scheme consistent with wave function collapse.

However, he did not prove the necessity of such a collapse.

Although von Neumann’s projection postulate is often presented as a normative description of quantum measurement, it was conceived by taking into account experimental evidence available during the 1930s (in particular the Compton-Simon experiment was paradigmatic), but many important present-day measurement procedures do not satisfy it (so-called measurements of the 2nd kind)

.

The existence of the wave function collapse is required in

the Copenhagen interpretation

the objective collapse interpretations

the transactional interpretation

the von Neumann interpretation in which consciousness causes collapse

.

.

On the other hand, the collapse is considered a redundant or optional approximation in

the consistent histories approach, self-dubbed “Copenhagen done right”

the Bohm interpretation

the many-worlds interpretation

the ensemble interpretation

.

The cluster of phenomena described by the expression wave function collapse is a fundamental problem in the interpretation of quantum mechanics, and is known as the measurement problem.

The problem is deflected by the Copenhagen Interpretation, which postulates that this is a special characteristic of the “measurement” process.

Everett’s many-worlds interpretation deals with it by discarding the collapse-process, thus reformulating the relation between measurement apparatus and system in such a way that the linear laws of quantum mechanics are universally valid;

that is, the only process according to which a quantum system evolves is governed by the Schrödinger equation or some relativistic equivalent.

Originating from de Broglie–Bohm theory, but no longer tied to it, is the physical process of decoherence, which causes an apparent collapse.

Decoherence is also important for the consistent histories interpretation.

A general description of the evolution of quantum mechanical systems is possible by using density operators and quantum operations.

In this formalism (which is closely related to the C*-algebraic formalism) the collapse of the wave function corresponds to a non-unitary quantum operation.

The significance ascribed to the wave function varies from interpretation to interpretation, and varies even within an interpretation (such as the Copenhagen Interpretation).

If the wave function merely encodes an observer’s knowledge of the universe then the wave function collapse corresponds to the receipt of new information.

This is somewhat analogous to the situation in classical physics, except that the classical “wave function” does not necessarily obey a wave equation.

If the wave function is physically real, in some sense and to some extent, then the collapse of the wave function is also seen as a real process, to the same extent

.

.

See also

Arrow of time

Interpretations of quantum mechanics
Quantum decoherence
Quantum interference
Quantum Zeno effect
Schrödinger’s cat
Stern–Gerlach experiment
Notes
Unless the observable being measured commutes with the Hamiltonian, the post-measurement state will in general evolve as time progresses into a superposition of different energy eigenstates as governed by the Schrödinger equation. Unless the state projected onto upon measurement has a definite energy value, the probability of having the same measurement outcome a non-zero time later will in general be less than one.
References
J. von Neumann (1932). Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik (in German). Berlin: Springer.
J. von Neumann (1955). Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press.
Schlosshauer, Maximilian (2005). “Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics”. Rev. Mod. Phys. 76 (4): 1267–1305. arXiv:quant-ph/0312059. Bibcode:2004RvMP…76.1267S. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267. S2CID 7295619.
Giacosa, Francesco (2014). “On unitary evolution and collapse in quantum mechanics”. Quanta. 3 (1): 156–170. arXiv:1406.2344. doi:10.12743/quanta.v3i1.26. S2CID 55705326.
Zurek, Wojciech Hubert (2009). “Quantum Darwinism”. Nature Physics. 5 (3): 181–188. arXiv:0903.5082. Bibcode:2009NatPh…5..181Z. doi:10.1038/nphys1202. S2CID 119205282.
Heisenberg, W. (1927). Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik, Z. Phys. 43: 172–198. Translation as ‘The actual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics’ here
G. Jaeger (2017). “”Wave-Packet Reduction” and the Quantum Character of the Actualization of Potentia”. Entropy. 19 (10): 13. Bibcode:2017Entrp..19..513J. doi:10.3390/e19100513.
Griffiths, David J. (2005). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, 2e. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. pp. 106–109. ISBN 0131118927.
Griffiths, David J. (2005). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, 2e. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall. pp. 100–105. ISBN 0131118927.
Wojciech H. Zurek (2003). “Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical”. Reviews of Modern Physics. 75 (3): 715. arXiv:quant-ph/0105127. Bibcode:2003RvMP…75..715Z. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.75.715. S2CID 14759237.
C. Kiefer (2002). “On the interpretation of quantum theory—from Copenhagen to the present day”. arXiv:quant-ph/0210152.
G. Jaeger (2017). “”Wave-Packet Reduction” and the Quantum Character of the Actualization of Potentia”. Entropy. 19 (10): 13. Bibcode:2017Entrp..19..513J. doi:10.3390/e19100513.
W. Pauli (1958). “Die allgemeinen Prinzipien der Wellenmechanik”. In S. Flügge (ed.). Handbuch der Physik (in German). V. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. p. 73.
L. Landau & R. Peierls (1931). “Erweiterung des Unbestimmtheitsprinzips für die relativistische Quantentheorie”. Zeitschrift für Physik (in German). 69 (1–2): 56–69. Bibcode:1931ZPhy…69…56L. doi:10.1007/BF01391513. S2CID 123160388.)
Discussions of measurements of the second kind can be found in most treatments on the foundations of quantum mechanics, for instance, J. M. Jauch (1968). Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Addison-Wesley. p. 165.; B. d’Espagnat (1976). Conceptual Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. W. A. Benjamin. pp. 18, 159.; and W. M. de Muynck (2002). Foundations of Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist Approach. Kluwer Academic Publishers. section 3.2.4..
External links
Quotations related to Wave function collapse at Wikiquote
vte
Quantum mechanics
Background
IntroductionHistory timelineGlossaryClassical mechanicsOld quantum theory
Fundamentals
Bra–ket notationCasimir effectCoherenceCoherent controlComplementarityDensity matrixEnergy level degenerate levelsexcited stateground stateQED vacuumQCD vacuumVacuum stateZero-point energyHamiltonianHeisenberg uncertainty principlePauli exclusion principleMeasurementObservableOperatorProbability distributionQuantumQubitQutritScattering theorySpinSpontaneous parametric down-conversionSymmetrySymmetry breaking Spontaneous symmetry breakingNo-go theoremNo-cloning theoremVon Neumann entropyWave interferenceWave function collapseUniversal wavefunctionWave–particle duality Matter waveWave propagationVirtual particle
Quantum
quantum coherenceannealingdecoherenceentanglementfluctuationfoamlevitationnoisenonlocalitynumberrealmstatesuperpositionsystemtunnellingQuantum vacuum state
Mathematics
Equations
DiracKlein–GordonPauliRydbergSchrödinger
Formulations
HeisenbergInteractionMatrix mechanicsPath integral formulationPhase spaceSchrödinger
Other
Quantum algebracalculus differentialstochasticgeometrygroupQ-analog List
Interpretations
BayesianConsistent historiesCosmologicalCopenhagende Broglie–BohmEnsembleHidden variablesMany worldsObjective collapseQuantum logicRelationalStochasticTransactional
Experiments
AfsharBell’s inequalityCold Atom LaboratoryDavisson–GermerDelayed-choice quantum eraserDouble-slitElitzur–VaidmanFranck–Hertz experimentLeggett–Garg inequalityMach-Zehnder inter.PopperQuantum eraserQuantum suicide and immortalitySchrödinger’s catStern–GerlachWheeler’s delayed choice
Science
Measurement problemQBism
Quantum
biologychemistrychaoscognitioncomplexity theorycomputing Timelinecosmologydynamicseconomicsfinancefoundationsgame theoryinformationnanosciencemetrologymindopticsprobabilitysocial sciencespacetime
Technologies
Quantum technology linksMatrix isolationPhase qubitQuantum dot cellular automatondisplaylasersingle-photon sourcesolar cellQuantum well laser
Extensions
Dirac seaFractional quantum mechanicsQuantum electrodynamics linksQuantum geometryQuantum field theory linksQuantum gravity linksQuantum information science linksQuantum statistical mechanicsRelativistic quantum mechanicsDe Broglie–Bohm theoryStochastic electrodynamics
Related
Quantum mechanics of time travelTextbooks
Category CategoryPortal Physics PortalWikiProject Physics WikiProjectCommons page Commons
Categories: Concepts in physicsQuantum measurement
Navigation menu
Not logged in
Talk
Contributions
Create account
Log in
ArticleTalk
ReadEditView historySearch
Search Wikipedia
Main page
Contents
Current events
Random article
About Wikipedia
Contact us
Donate
Contribute
Help
Learn to edit
Community portal
Recent changes
Upload file
Tools
What links here
Related changes
Special pages
Permanent link
Page information
Cite this page
Wikidata item
Print/export
Download as PDF
Printable version
In other projects
Wikiquote

Languages
العربية
Deutsch
Español
Français
Italiano
Português
Русский
Tagalog
中文
18 more
Edit links
This page was last edited on 17 November 2020, at 18:49 (UTC).
Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
Privacy policyAbout WikipediaDisclaimersContact WikipediaMobile viewDevelopersStatisticsCookie statementWikimedia FoundationPowered by MediaWiki

Wave function collapse

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Jump to navigationJump to search

For other uses, see Collapse.

Part of a series on

Quantum mechanics

{\displaystyle i\hbar {\frac {\partial }{\partial t}}|\psi (t)\rangle ={\hat {H}}|\psi (t)\rangle }{\displaystyle i\hbar {\frac {\partial }{\partial t}}|\psi (t)\rangle ={\hat {H}}|\psi (t)\rangle }

Schrödinger equation

IntroductionGlossaryHistoryTextbooks

Background[show]

Fundamentals[show]

Effects[show]

Experiments[show]

Formulations[show]

Equations[show]

Interpretations[show]

Advanced topics[show]

Scientists[show]

Categories[show]

vte

.

.

*👨‍🔬🕵️‍♀️🙇‍♀️*SKETCHES*🙇‍♂️👩‍🔬🕵️‍♂️*

.

📚📖|/\-*WIKI-LINK*-/\|📖📚

.

.

👈👈👈☜*WAVE MEASUREMENTS* ☞ 👉👉👉

.

.

💕💝💖💓🖤💙🖤💙🖤💙🖤❤️💚💛🧡❣️💞💔💘❣️🧡💛💚❤️🖤💜🖤💙🖤💙🖤💗💖💝💘

.

.

*🌈✨ *TABLE OF CONTENTS* ✨🌷*

.

.

🔥🔥🔥🔥🔥🔥*we won the war* 🔥🔥🔥🔥🔥🔥